Skip to main content

A half century of electronic fetal monitoring and bioethics: silence speaks louder than words

Abstract

Bioethics abolished the prevailing Hippocratic tenet instructing physicians to make treatment decisions, replacing it with autonomy through informed consent. Informed consent allows the patient to choose treatment after options are explained by the physician. The appearance of bioethics in 1970 coincided with the introduction of electronic fetal monitoring (EFM), which evolved to become the fetal surveillance modality of choice for virtually all women in labor. Autonomy rapidly pervaded all medical procedures, but there was a clear exemption for EFM. Even today, EFM remains immune to the doctrine of informed consent despite continually mounting evidence which proves the procedure is nothing more than myth, illusion and junk science that subjects mothers and babies alike to increased risks of morbidity and mortality. And ethicists have remained utterly silent through a half century of EFM misuse. Our article explores this egregious ethical failure by reviewing EFM’s lack of clinical efficacy, discussing the EFM related harm to mothers and babies, and focusing on the reasons that this obstetrical procedure eluded the revolutionary change from the Hippocratic tradition to autonomy through informed consent.

Background

“Declare the past, diagnose the present, foretell the future. As to diseases, make a habit of two things—to help and not to harm.” From the book Epidemics I

Fifty years ago electronic fetal monitoring (EFM) became an overnight sensation when first introduced into labor suites. Declared to be the long awaited cerebral palsy (CP) cure [1], EFM, in a very short time, was virtually the sole monitoring method used in the industrialized world, the raison d’etre of fetal surveillance in labor [2,3,4,5]. And today EFM remains obstetrics’ deus ex machine [6] despite overwhelming and damning scientific evidence that EFM theory is nothing more than myth and wishful thinking [7,8,9,10,11,12,13,14,15,16,17,18] and despite evidence that CP is caused chiefly by prenatal factors operating before labor begins, that CP is not preventable by any response to EFM patterns, that EFM has never reduced the rate of CP in 50 years of intense use and supposed improvement [4,5,6,7,8,9,10,11,12,13, 15,16,17,18,19,20,21,22,23,24,25,26,27,28,29,30,31], and that EFM use has and is today causing more harm to mothers and babies that it has ever helped [5, 8, 9, 12, 13, 17].

At almost the same instant that EFM became a clinical sensation, bioethics, a word coined in the 1960s, became a recognized entity, linking scientific advances to human values [32]. The foundation of bioethics was autonomy—a person’s right to choose or refuse medical treatment based on informed consent—replacing the centuries-old deontology based on the Hippocratic tradition of benign paternalism—the physician’s duty is to choose the treatment for the patient [32,33,34,35].

Linking EFM use with the new bioethics should have been a seamless affair following Thomas Kuhn’s six stages of scientific revolution resulting in his now famous paradigm shift from the old to the new [36]. And while this shift to the new bioethics indeed occurred in most medical arenas [32,33,34,35], it failed utterly with EFM and obstetrics. Today obstetrical EFM use without mothers’ informed consent is the epitome of medical paternalism. The cause of this momentous failure was the confluence of three powerful influences that even the brilliant Kuhn failed to see on the horizon.

Throughout EFM’s rise to deus ex machina and its evasion of autonomy-informed consent, the clinical evidence against EFM rose up like a mammoth volcanic ocean island, plain for all to see [5,6,7,8,9,10,11,12,13,14,15,16,17,18,19,20,21,22,23,24,25,26,27,28,29,30,31]. And while a few clinicians were bold enough to challenge the EFM medical establishment that insisted on continued EFM use despite the evidence of harm, evidence that should have provoked bioethical outrage, the bioethics community’s silence was deafening and remains so today. The question is, why the silence?

And just as important a question is, could bioethics, having no enforcement mechanisms other than words, forced the EFM establishment to recognize autonomy-informed consent and rescued those mothers who believed in EFM’s magic powers only because they were never told the truth about EFM? The answer is yes. As will be demonstrated, bioethical silence is louder that its words, but if words had at least been spoken and written bioethics could have changed forever the EFM dynamic just as Kuhn foretold.

In the beginning

“To help and not to harm” has been an integral part of medicine from the very first attempts to organize medicine into books and explain theories of disease and the moral, ethical wisdom associated with healing and healers [32]. The thought is perhaps more familiar when written, “first do no harm,” and while both phrases have obscure origins, they have been repeated as part of the Hippocratic tradition by many Western physician commentators and teachers throughout the centuries [32,33,34, 37]. Repeated not only in writings and lectures, but also formalized in various ethics codes like Percival’s Code, the codes of early medical societies, the first AMA Code in 1847, and just about all subsequent ethics codes of Western-oriented medical societies [32]. It is curious, however, why it was necessary to warn physicians not to harm their patients when the idea of helping patients is dominant. The idea of doing no harm, however, becomes apparent when the second Hippocratic medical principle is considered—it is the physician who must decide what is best for the patient according to the physician’s ability and judgment [32,33,34].

Thus, Western ethics through the ages was dominated by Hippocratic medical paternalism—physician-centered medicine [38]. Oliver Wendell Holmes, addressing an 1871 medical school graduating class, advised the physicians to conform to the Hippocratic tradition and conceal almost everything from patients, saying that the patient had no right to the truth [38]. In the 1930s, when a patient asked the physician a question during an examination, the physician “slapped her face, saying, ‘I’ll ask the questions here. I’ll do the talking.’” [38] In 1944, President Roosevelt’s physicians did not reveal to him their diagnosis of elevated blood pressure and congestive heart failure diagnoses, a year before a stroke took his life [39]. In 1961, a published study revealed that 88% of U.S. physicians surveyed did not tell the truth to terminally ill cancer patients [33, 38]. And it was not until 1981 that AMA revised its Principles of Medical Ethics to revise the previously accepted Hippocratic-approved lying to patients, mandating that physicians were required to deal honestly with patients and colleagues [33].

This was the state of the centuries-old medical ethics milieu in 1960, when, amid unimagined breakthroughs in science, medicine, and technology, medical inventors worked to perfect an electronic fetal monitor that could, so they believed, predict fetal distress and prevent cerebral palsy [1, 2]. It was a milieu in which physicians were viewed by themselves and the public as being superior to patients and most others in knowledge and insight. Physicians were authoritarian, determining what was in the patients’ best interests, even if the patients did not agree [34].

Deus ex machina

Thus, in 1970, when EFM was introduced into clinical practice [2], obstetricians were comfortable operating in the Hippocratic sphere in which they made all medical decisions without input from patients. There was, therefore, no necessity to inform patients that EFM was totally experimental and had never been proven in even one clinical trial [5,6,7,8,9,10,11,12,13,14,15,16,17]. Nor was there any necessity to advise patients that the very foundational theories undergirding EFM—fetal heart rate reflected past and present fetal brain function and oxygen deprivation in labor was the sole cause of CP—were unscientific myths handed down from generation to generation and untested by modern medicine [4, 5, 7,8,9,10,11,12,13, 15,16,17,18, 20,21,22,23,24,25,26,27,28]. Rather, obstetricians throughout the industrialized world accepted the new monitor as the machine that would, as its proponents assured the world, reduce by half intrapartum deaths, mental retardation, and CP [1]. There was no necessity for informed consent, because that concept is a product of bioethics, which, in 1970, had only just emerged as a deontology that would eventually overtake the Hippocratic tradition [32,33,34]. While simple consent—the patient may say “yes” or “no” to a surgery—was a legal concept [38, 40], true informed consent, the product of bioethics and autonomy [33,34,35], lay in the future. Thus, when it came to employing the new EFM, obstetricians continued in the Hippocratic physician-is-dominant tradition. And, unfortunately, as will be seen, obstetricians and EFM have continued in the Hippocratic tradition despite the fact that overwhelming evidence demonstrates EFM use has done more harm than good for mothers and babies during the last 50 years.

A new deontology

Immanuel Kant is credited with the development of deontological ethical theory, a result of enlightenment rationalism and liberal political philosophy, the central focus of which is the individual’s liberties and rights [33]. This liberal political philosophy bypassed Western medicine, however, until after World War II, when a series of disclosures, beginning with the Nuremburg trials and disclosure of wartime medical experiments, began to focus attention on medical research conducted without patients’ consent [33, 34, 41]. The Tuskegee syphilis study, plutonium injections by Manhattan Project doctors, radioactive iodine trials, and a host of other human experiments, 22 of which were exposed in Henry Beecher’s 1966 groundbreaking whistleblower exposé, shocked the public [41]. The common denominator of these medical experiments was that meaningful consent was never obtained from the patients [38, 41].

These experiments and their public exposure, along with other societal upheavals in the 1950s and ‘60s, caused physicians, scientists, philosophers, religious and legal scholars, and other disciplines, to come together to focus on the moral, ethical, and philosophical ambiguities presented by the dizzying array of worldwide scientific medical advances [32,33,34,35, 38]. This new discipline, said to have been born around 1970 [32,33,34], soon took on a new name—bioethics.

This new deontology, based on duty, was dominated by one overwhelming theme—autonomy—respect for the individual and individual self-rule, a duty, fidelity, and faithfulness of one human being to another [34], such that the individual patient could meaningfully choose her medical treatment based on knowledge of the choices available inputted by the physician. And while the term “informed consent” had been used before bioethics was born, from 1970 on, that term was inculcated with new meaning, becoming synonymous with autonomy and driving medicine’s focus away from Hippocratic physician-centered medicine to patient-centered medicine, where it remains today [32,33,34, 38]. Closely associated with this first bioethics principle are two duties—non-maleficence—do not impose unnecessary harm or risk of harm—and beneficence—dedication to the patient’s welfare, a positive medical goal different in substantial degree from merely avoiding harm [32,33,34,35, 38].

While there are still many controversies over the exact meaning and reach of these and other bioethical duties and obligations, it is clear that medicine’s primary bioethical, moral duty is to enable patients to make their own medical decisions, perhaps even wrong in the physician’s judgment, decisions based on relevant, current information provided by the physician [32,33,34,35, 38]. And while it is assumed that a given number of patients will not want the burden of deciding, that does not diminish the physician’s duty to provide the information to all patients—in other words, meaningful, informed consent is a moral imperative [33, 34]. This imperative and much of bioethics was, of course, the antithesis of the Hippocratic traditions that had dominated medicine for centuries, yet bioethical thinking became dominant in medicine in only a few short years. A paradigm shift occurred in almost all aspects of medicine, save and except one—electronic fetal monitoring.

The revolution

Science is always progressing. New theories become settled science and old theories disappear. Ptolemy’s math was impeccable. His calculations were subject to multiple proofs by scholars for well over a thousand years. The conclusion was the same—the earth was the center of the universe. Not so, said Copernicus. Geocentricity was a myth. Real-world cosmology was heliocentric—the sun was the center of the universe. There were few believers. The myth had stood the test of time. One hundred years later, Galileo confirmed the new cosmology with a telescope.

The Copernican revolution was Thomas Kuhn’s prime example of how science is driven to change [36]. In normal periods of science, a paradigm exists by which certain anomalies can be solved. But a crisis in science arises when confidence is lost in a paradigm’s ability to solve particularly worrisome anomalies, and thus a scientific revolution occurs by which an existing paradigm is superseded by a rival.

Before Kuhn, there was little to explain how science changes. There was, however, a conception of scientific change as a smooth, flowing addition of new truths to the stock of old truths and an occasional correction of past errors. According to Kuhn’s theory, science is not uniform, but has normal and revolutionary or extraordinary phases, which he referred to as the puzzle-solving power of the competing ideas. But these competing theories, according to Kuhn, are generally incommensurable, because they share very little commonality [36]. And so it was that Kuhn’s scientific revolution perfectly presaged the medical ethics revolution from the Hippocratic paradigm to the bioethics paradigm.

As we have seen, the bioethics paradigm shift occurred when the Hippocratic ethics was found inadequate to solve the exposés related to medical human experimentation without consent, as well as other patient centering problems [32,33,34,35, 38]. The change from Hippocratic ethics to bioethics was extremely rapid when compared to Kuhn’s Copernican revolution and other examples of scientific paradigm shift, but the paradigm shift to bioethics did indeed follow Kuhn’s theory. Autonomy replaced physician-centered medicine, hospital ethics committees were created, institutional review boards were appointed, and many other dynamic changes occurred in the practice of medicine and the field of medical scientific research [33,34,35]. But while many things changed, at least one thing stayed the same—electronic fetal monitoring, an experimental machine, is still used today without the informed consent of mothers and with no explanation of the conflict of interest physicians have with respect to continued EFM use despite a half-century of uncontradicted proof that EFM does more harm than good.

Is EFM really experimental?

EFM began clinical life with only a few detractors questioning its basic premise [42]—the conventional but unproven wisdom that CP and neurologic birth maladies were caused by birth asphyxia, hypoxia, and cerebral ischemia, which were reflected in out-of-norm fetal heart rate that, if stopped in time—by C-section or instrumented delivery—would prevent CP and birth maladies [4, 5, 7,8,9,10,11]. Most physicians simply accepted EFM inventors’ claims and promises, even though EFM inventors skipped the rigors of the scientific method and the crucible of randomized clinical trials, and introduced EFM with no instruction manual, with unrealistic efficacy expectations, and no clearly defined parameters for use [43]. As EFM accelerated in use to 85% of births in the United States [5], more and more vehement criticism appeared following its first clinical use. Criticism completely ignored by most physicians and their birth related professional organizations (BRPOs) worldwide as well as ethicists [5, 7,8,9, 25].

When EFM was subjected to 12 clinical trials versus auscultation beginning in 1976, EFM showed no benefit, but only a dramatic increase in C-sections due to EFM’s 99% false-positive rate [7, 11, 19, 26,27,28,29]. In the 1970s, critics wrote that EFM use is unjustified by any evidence [44, 45]. In the 1980s, critics wrote that EFM is increasing unnecessary C-sections [46], and the procedure should be abandoned [46]. In the 1990s, critics wrote that because of EFM and medical malpractice liability concerns, United States obstetricians were performing cesarean sections at a rate much higher than anywhere else in the world; [47] EFM is nothing but a disappointing story, and the hoped-for EFM benefit has not been realized; [48] EFM promised much but achieved little because fetal heart rate changes reflect neurologic insult earlier in pregnancy, not intrapartum events; [49] and no data exists that intervention based on any EFM patterns has reduced CP [49]. By the turn of the century, the critics became even more vocal as the evidence proved CP was not caused by birth events and EFM was not in any manner efficacious, but indeed harmful, primarily because it triggered unnecessary C-sections with the attendant morbidity and mortality: tests leading to unnecessary abdominal surgery in 99% of cases is absurd; [17] EFM has done more harm than good to mothers and babies; [17] EFM has had no effect on perinatal mortality or neurologic morbidity; [26] EFM interpretation is subjective, difficult to standardize, and poorly reproducible; [6] after almost 50 years, there is no consensus on EFM pattern interpretation and management; [3] EFM as a screening tool for absence of harm is no better than tossing a coin; [12] EFM overall caused more harm than good; [12] there is a growing consensus in the maternal-fetal medicine community that it is time to start over with EFM and establish a common language, standard interpretation and management principles [43]. In 2014, the authors of Neonatal Encephalopathy and Neurologic Outcome, Second Edition, published by ACOG and American Academy of Pediatrics, and assisted by an international array of Task Force consultants, conceded EFM defeat after a concerted 50-year effort to make EFM predict asphyxia, hypoxia, ischemia, acidemia, CP, and neurologic injury: “There are no long-term benefits of EFM as currently used” [21] (at 88); “no evidence exists demonstrating that electronic FHR monitoring reduces the rate of neonatal encephalopathy” [21] (at 92); “there is no evidence in the current literature to support the ability of practitioners to predict neonatal neurologic injury, cerebral palsy, or stillbirth using EFM” [21] (at 91); “cesarean delivery as an obstetrical intervention to reduce neonatal encephalopathy and cerebral palsy has been considered unsuccessful” [21] (at 104). This Task Force report was endorsed not only by ACOG and AAP, but also by 11 other worldwide birth-related organizations from Australia, New Zealand, Japan, Canada, and the United States [21].

Even today, efforts to make EFM heel to command have failed once more. EFM assisted by ST-segment analysis did not improve perinatal outcomes or decrease C-section rates [50], which are now 33% in the United States [51] and even higher in other parts of the world [5]. And more voices are calling on BRPOs to condemn EFM use in both labor rooms and in CP-EFM worldwide litigation because it is junk science [5, 7,8,9,10,11,12,13, 15,16,17, 19, 25, 43, 52]. Other voices are calling to reduce the C-section rate recognized to be caused in large part by defensive medicine and EFM’s 99% false positive rate [12, 53, 54], which subjects mothers and babies to unnecessary morbidity and mortality risks from not only the immediate surgery but from subsequent sequela [5, 8, 9, 12, 13, 17]. And other voices are citing increasing evidence that C-sections are exposing babies to the specter of subsequent lifelong chronic diseases and neuropsychiatric disorders [55,56,57,58].

A practical, common sense definition of experimental medical procedures would be that until the published, peer-reviewed medical evidence regarding risks, benefits, and overall safety and efficacy demonstrate that the procedure has a beneficial effect on healthcare outcomes, the procedure is experimental. It is without question that the unrefuted evidence over five decades has proven EFM is unsafe, un-efficacious, and has no beneficial effect on healthcare outcomes. Just the opposite. EFM does little good, but considerable harm. Thus, it is unfathomable that the ACOG-AAP Task Force [21] and individual practitioners in many countries continue to call for EFM use in every labor [2, 59,60,61].

Why?

Vincible ignorance

It is no longer a secret why BRPOs, medical societies, and individual physicians and hospitals ignored the 50-year EFM volcano erupting with undeniable, unrefuted evidence that EFM is junk science and causes harm to mothers and babies. The secret has been exposed in government studies [62, 63], medical journals [4, 7, 9, 11, 12, 15, 16, 19, 23, 43, 47, 53, 54], legal journals [5, 25, 64,65,66,67], newspaper and popular magazine articles [68, 69] since at least 1979: obstetrical defensive medicine. Physicians and hospitals use EFM because they believe it protects them from trial lawyers and CP lawsuits. This concept of EFM providing malpractice protection is, and always has been, another birth myth, as has been pointed out in the medical and legal literature for many years [5, 8, 25, 52, 64,65,66]. But, like the other birth myths, the truth would destroy the collective obstetrical illusions handed down from generation to generation. But clinging to obstetrical illusions and myths is merely practicing nineteenth century medicine, which was based on whim, personal belief, and bias, rather than evidence-based, scientific-based medicine. It also violates every past and current concept in bioethics, especially the heart and soul of bioethics—autonomy.

So the question arises, why did bioethics issue an ethical pass to EFM? How did virtually all of medicine succumb to Kuhn’s paradigm shift from Hippocratic ethics to bioethics in just a few decades, while EFM continues to be used without informed consent, continues to cause harm without discernible benefits, and all without raising any concern or alarm from the bioethics community? Who issued EFM the ethics pass?

In plain sight

Although it is impossible to determine the moment that paternalism died and autonomy was born, we can isolate one period in early EFM history when autonomy was recognized as dominant over paternalistic EFM use. That dominance quickly faded, however, because of influences unforeseen and unaccounted for by contemporary scholars—trial lawyers, medical malpractice lawsuits, and defensive medicine.

In the 1970s, NIH organized consensus-development Task Forces to address recent developments in medical research and practice [62]. One Task Force on predictors of intrapartum fetal distress was composed of physicians, sociologists, lawyers, and ethicists, among others. The Task Force’s 1979 report was subsequently published in three prominent journals [62]. With respect to EFM, the Task Force recommended, because there was no evidence of EFM efficacy, that mothers be informed, during the course of prenatal care and again on admission to the labor suite, about EFM limitations and risks [62]. This Task Force’s EFM bioethical recommendation was followed by the International Federation of Gynecology and Obstetrics and Family Health International (FIGO) in 1986 in their Guidelines for Fetal Monitoring Use: “Mothers should have the opportunity to discuss the use of electronic fetal heart rate monitoring during antepartum care and again upon admission to hospital in labor, so that they are able to give or to withhold informed consent.” [70].

But informed consent never happened. With these two exceptions, EFM medical literature and BRPOs are completely silent regarding when, how, and what to tell mothers about EFM’s limitations and risks and, as the evidence increased in later years, about EFM’s morbidity and mortality, current and future. There is also complete silence in the bioethical literature urging BRPOs and physicians to make EFM informed consent a duty. The EFM informed consent issue did not escape the nursing, midwife, and legal literature [65, 66, 71, 72], and, in fact, is still discussed today [67, 73, 74]. But these voices have been ignored by obstetricians and ethicists alike.

Murphy’s law and paradigm shifts

Kuhn started challenging the scholarly community with his revolutionary science, paradigms, and puzzle-solving in his 1962 book, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions [36]. While Kuhn’s revolution model perfectly presaged the coming bioethical paradigm shift, a retrospective view reveals that Kuhn, his proponents, and critics alike overlooked a paradigm shift taking place under their feet—trial lawyers, medical malpractice, and defensive medicine.

In the 1960s, for reasons still debated today, there was a sudden, dramatic rise in the frequency and severity of medical malpractice lawsuits and claims, which accelerated rapidly to unprecedented levels, precipitating the first of many medical malpractice-insurance coverage crises early in the 1970s [5, 8, 9, 25]. Obstetrics was a particular target because, until EFM, the only evidence of fetal heart rate during labor had been the obstetrician’s recollection. With EFM, there was a permanent paper tracing that trial lawyers’ courtroom experts could interpret years and even decades after a birth and, of course, inevitably find the precise moment the inattentive or ignorant attending physician should have performed a C-section to save what the courtroom experts said was a neurologically perfect infant from lifelong crippling injuries. EFM, nobly conceived, met Murphy’s Law, and for 50 years has been the trial lawyer’s weapon to extract billions from physicians and hospitals the world over, even as the evidence mounted that EFM did not predict CP and CP was not caused primarily by asphyxia, anoxia, hypoxia, or ischemia during birth. On the other hand, physicians, new at the litigation game, ironically adopted the trial lawyers’ preferred weapon, EFM, as their sole CP-lawsuit defense [5, 8, 9, 25]. But over the past half-century, physicians worldwide have lost the CP-EFM battle to the trial lawyers for a variety of reasons [5, 8, 9, 25] and are now engulfed in an epidemic explosion of malpractice lawsuits, especially CP-EFM neurologic impairment birth-injury lawsuits [5, 7,8,9,10,11, 15, 25].

The result of the initial trial lawyers versus doctors litigation battle was defensive medicine—prophylactic medicine of little use to the patient, administered primarily for the protection of doctors and hospitals from trial lawyers and lawsuits [5, 7,8,9,10,11, 23, 25]. And while most defensive medicine received considerable criticism from bioethicists, economists, and some clinicians as being medically and ethically questionable, not to mention costly to society [75,76,77,78], the EFM criticism, as we have seen, came only from a small number of clinicians and scholars, and even they never addressed the bioethical issue of physicians violating patient autonomy by EFM use without informed consent. Ethicists defaulted in the EFM debate by their overwhelming silence. The use of a scientifically bankrupt machine solely to protect healthcare providers from trial lawyers and lawsuits when the machine is known to be harming mothers and babies is an egregious conflict of interest and outrageous endorsement of obstetrical defensive medicine—post-modern ethical relativism solely to benefit healthcare providers—and is undeniable proof that evidence-based standard of care and bioethical principles are nothing more than empty rhetoric [79, 80].

A part of bioethical morality requires that patients be allowed autonomy and that in the treatment process the physician refrain from harm to the extent practical. But the third principle—beneficence—requires more than avoiding harm. It requires positive steps to benefit the patient, steps that balance benefits, risks, costs, and other patient goals to produce the most optimum results possible [33, 34]. In other words, beneficence requires the physician to favor the patient’s interest over the physician’s self-interest [33, 34]. This obligation is fidelity. It results in a fiduciary relationship between patient and physician [33, 34]. In daily practice, this fiduciary relationship is often challenged by potential divided loyalties—conflicts of interest—to the physician’s colleagues, institutions, third parties, funding sources, and the physician’s self-protection interests [33, 34]. Conflicts of interest have received enormous attention, primarily due to perceived conflicts in commercial, manufacturing, and financial relationships [33, 34]. However, the EFM conflict of interest—using a device that actually causes harm to patients primarily to protect doctors and hospitals from CP lawsuits—is enormously more compromising than gifts, trips, and money, because it has been and is hidden from public view and because the EFM device is fraudulently presented to mothers as a safety device necessary for a healthy baby. Fidelity could not possibly be more compromised.

Ethicists’ silence on a woman’s right to EFM truth and her right to choose what happens to her body and to her baby has spoken more loudly than words ever could.

Conclusion - POST TENEBRAS LUX

Law and bioethics are separate, distinct entities. Law is more structured, concerning itself with rules that stabilize society’s social institutions and structures. Law concentrates on the criminal and civil penalties to be brought to bear on miscreants who fail to conform [33, 34]. Bioethics, on the other hand, are conceived of as moral rules and ideals—how one ought to act toward others—some aspirational and some even unobtainable. How seriously these moral rules must be taken is still in dispute among the ethical legalists and ethical antinomianists [33, 34], but neither extreme in that debate contradicts the fact that ethical rules are essentially unenforceable save for the mild, occasional organizational enforcement and perhaps occasional licensing rebuke.

But perhaps bioethics’ unenforceability is actually an illusion. After all, at the dawn of bioethics there was no enforceability other than words and public exposure of medical procedures that most agreed were morally wrong and dismissive of individual autonomy. Bioethics changed the entirety of medicine and the Hippocratic tradition that had ruled for centuries. Words were the only weapons needed. So the question arises, can words still be used to change the EFM bioethics? Said another way, can bioethics shed light in the darkness of 50 years of EFM paternalism? It would be a far better thing to voluntarily come to the light of EFM autonomy-informed consent now, rather than being forced into the light tomorrow by the trial lawyers.

Abbreviations

BRPO:

Birth related professional organizations

CP:

Cerebral palsy

EFM:

Electronic fetal monitoring

References

  1. Quilligan EJ, Paul RH. Fetal monitoring: is it worth it? Obstet Gynecol. 1975;45(1):96–100.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  2. Freeman RK, Garite TJ, Nageotte MP, Miller LA. Fetal heat rate monitoring. 4th ed. Philadelphia: Lippincott Williams & Wilkins; 2012.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Parer JT. Personalities, politics, and territorial tiffs: a half century of fetal heart rate monitoring. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 2011;204(6):548–50.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  4. Jenkins HML. Thirty years of electronic intrapartum fetal heart rate monitoring: discussion paper. J Royal Soc Med. 1989;82:210–4.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  5. Sartwelle TP. Electronic fetal monitoring: a bridge too far. J Legal Med. 2012;33:313–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Greene MF. Obstetricians still await a deus ex machina. New Engl J Med. 2006;355(21):2247–8.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  7. MacLennan AH, Thompson SC, Gecz J. Cerebral palsy – causes, pathways, and the role of genetic variants. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 2015;213(6):779–88.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  8. Sartwelle TP, Johnston JC. Neonatal encephalopathy 2015: opportunity lost and words unspoken. J Maternal-Fetal & Neonatal Med. 2016;29(9):1372–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Sartwelle TP, Johnston JC. Cerebral palsy litigation: change course or abandon ship. J Child Neurol. 2015;30(7):828–41.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  10. Donn SM, Chiswick ML, Fanaroff JM. Medico-legal implications of hypoxic-ischemic birth injury. Semin Fetal Neonatal Med. 2014;19(5):317–21.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  11. Badawi N, Keogh JM. Causal pathways in cerebral palsy. J Pediatrics and Child Health. 2013;49:58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Constantine MM, Saade GR. The first caesarean: role of “fetal distress” diagnosis. Semin Perinatol. 2012;36:379–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Grimes DA, Peipert JF. Electronic fetal monitoring as a public health screening program: the arithmetic of failure. Obstet Gynecol. 2010;116(6):1397–400.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  14. Khalil A, O’Brien P. Fetal heart rate monitoring—is it a waste of time? Obstet & Gynecol Of India. 2006;56(6):481–5.

    Google Scholar 

  15. MacLennan A, Hankins G, Speer N. Only an expert witness can prevent cerebral palsy. Obstet Gynecol. 2006;8(1):28–30.

    Google Scholar 

  16. MacLennan A, Nelson KB, Hankins G, Speer N. Who will deliver our grandchildren? JAMA. 2005;294(13):1688–90.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  17. Clark S, Hankins G. Temporal and demographic trends in cerebral palsy—facts and fiction. Am J Obstet & Gynecol. 2003;188:628–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Beller FK. The cerebral palsy story: a catastrophic misunderstanding in obstetrics. Obstet Gynecol Survey. 1995;50:83–6.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  19. Nelson KB, Blair E. Prenatal factors in singletons with cerebral palsy born at or near term. New Eng. J. Med. 2015;373(10):946–53.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  20. Blair E, Nelson KB. Fetal growth restriction and risk of cerebral palsy in singletons born after at least 35 weeks’ gestation. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 2015;212(4):520e1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Am Coll Obstet & Gynecol & Am Acad. Pediatricians, neonatal encephalopathy and neurologic outcome. (2nd ed.) (2014).

  22. Ellenberg JH, Nelson KB. The association of cerebral palsy with birth asphyxia: a definitional quagmire. Devel Med & Child Neuro. 2013;55:210–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. MacLennan AH. A ‘no fault’ cerebral palsy pension scheme would benefit all Australians. Aust NZ J Obstet Gynecol. 2011;52(6):479–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Obladen M. Lame from birth: early concepts of cerebral palsy. J Child Neuro. 2011;26(2):248–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Sartwelle TP. Defending a neurologic birth injury: asphyxia neonatorum redux. J Legal Med. 2009;30(2):181–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Graham EM, Peterson SM, Christo DK, et al. Intrapartum electronic fetal heart rate monitoring and the prevention of perinatal brain injury. Obstet Gynecol. 2006;108(3):656–66.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  27. Am. Coll. Obstet. & Gynecol. & Am. Acad. Pediatricians, neonatal encephalopathy and cerebral palsy: defining the pathogenesis and pathophysiology (2003).

  28. MacLennan AH. A template for defining a causal relation between acute intrapartum events and cerebral palsy: international consensus statement. Br Med J. 1999;319:1054–9.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  29. Nelson KB, Dambrosia J, Ting TY, Grether JK. Uncertain value of electronic fetal monitoring in predicting cerebral palsy. New Engl. J. Med. 1996;334(10):613–8.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  30. Scheller JM, Nelson KB. Does cesarean delivery prevent cerebral palsy or other neurologic problems of childhood? Obstet Gynecol. 1994;83:624–30.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  31. Friedman EA. The obstetrician’s dilemma: how much fetal monitoring and cesarean section is enough? New Engl. J. Med. 1986;315(10):641–3.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  32. Jonsen AR. A short history of medical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Veatch RM. The basics of bioethics. 3rd ed. New Jersey: Pearson Education Inc; 2012.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of biomedical ethics. 7th ed. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Jecker NS, Jonsen AR, Pearlman RA. Bioethics. 3rd ed. Sudbury: Jones & Bartlett Learning LLC; 2012.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Kuhn TS. The structure of scientific revolutions, 50th anniversary edition with an introductory essay by Ian hacking. 4th ed. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press; 2012.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  37. Smith CM. Origin and uses of Primum non Nocere—above all do no harm! J Clin Pharmacology. 2005;45:371–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Laine C, Davidoff F. Patient-centered medicine. JAMA. 1996;275(2):152–6.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  39. Baron RJ. Professional self-regulation in a changing world. JAMA. 2015;313(18):1807–8.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  40. Chervenak J, McCullough LB, Chervenak FA. Surgery without consent or miscommunication? A new look at a landmark case. Am. J. Obstet. & Gynecol. 2015;212(5):586–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Beecher HK. Ethics and clinical research. New Eng. J. Med. 1966;274(24):1354–60.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  42. Benson RC, Schubeck F, Deutschberger J, et al. Fetal heart rate as a predictor of fetal distress: a report from the collaborative project. Obstet Gynecol. 1968;32:259–66.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  43. Clark SL, Nageotte MP, Garite TJ, et al. Intrapartum management of category II fetal heart rate tracings: toward standardization of care. Am J Obstet & Gynecol. 2013;209(2):89–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Banta HD, Thacker SB. Assessing the costs and benefits of electronic fetal monitoring. Obstet Gynecol Surv. 1979;34:627–42.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  45. Illingworth RS. Why blame the obstetrician: a review. Brit Med J. 1979;1(6166):797–801.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  46. Thacker SB. The efficacy of intrapartum electronic fetal monitoring. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 1987;156(1):24–30.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  47. Manuel BM. Professional liability—a no-fault solution. New Eng. J. Med. 1990;322(9):627–30.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  48. Freeman R. Intrapartum fetal monitoring—a disappointing story. New Eng. J. Med. 1990;322(9):624–6.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  49. MacDonald D. Cerebral palsy and intra-partum fetal monitoring. New Engl. J. Med. 1996;334(10):659–60.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  50. Belfort MA, Saade GR, Thom E, et al. A randomized trial of intrapartum fetal ECG ST-segment analysis. New Engl J Med. 2015;373(7):632–41.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  51. Osterman MJK, Kochanek KD, MaDorman MF, et al. Annual summary of vital statistics: 2012-2013. Pediatrics. 2015;135(6):1115–25.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  52. Maso G, Piccoli M, DeSeta F, et al. Intrapartum fetal heart monitoring interpretation in labour: a critical appraisal. Minerva Ginecol. 2015;67:65–79.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  53. Spong CY, Berghella V, Wenstrom KD, et al. Preventing the first cesarean delivery: summary of a joint Eunice Kennedy Shriver National Institute of Child Health and Human Development, Society for Maternal Fetal Medicine, and American College of Obstetrics and Gynecology Workshop. Obstet Gynecol. 2012;120:1181–93.

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  54. American College Obstetricians & Gynecologists and Society for Maternal Fetal Medicine. Safe prevention of the primary cesarean section. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 2014;123:179–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Sevelsted A, Stokholm J, Bonnelykke K, et al. Cesarean section and chronic immune disorders. Pediatrics. 2015;135(1):e92–8.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  56. Friedrich MJ. Unraveling the influence of gut microbes on the mind. JAMA. 2015;313(17):1699–701.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  57. Borre YE, O’Keeffe GW, Clarke G, et al. Microbiota and neurodevelopmental windows: implications for brain disorders. Trends Mol Med. 2014;20(9):509–18.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  58. Neu J. The pre- and early postnatal microbiome: relevance to subsequent health and disease. Neo Reviews. 2013;13(12):e-592–e599.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ayres-de-Campos D. Why is intrapartum foetal monitoring necessary—impact on outcomes and interventions. Best Pract Res Clin Obstet Gynecol 2016;30:3–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Nageotte MP. Fetal heart monitoring. Sem Fetal Neo Med. 2015;20(3):144–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Berkowitz RL, D’Alton ME, Goldberg JD, et al. The case for an electronic fetal heart rate monitoring credentialing examination. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 2014;210(3):204–7.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  62. Zuspan FP, Quilligan EJ, Iams JD, et al. NICHD consensus development task force report: predictors of intrapartum fetal distress—the role of electronic fetal monitoring. J Pediatrics. 1979;95(6):1026–30. See also Zuspan FP, Quilligan EJ, Iams JD, et al. Predictors of intrapartum fetal distress: The role of electronic fetal monitoring, Report of the National Institute of Child Health and Human Development Consensus Development Task Force. Am. J. Obstet. Gynecol. 1979; 135(3):287-291; Zuspan FP, Quilligan EJ, Iams JD et al. NICHD consensus development Task Force report. Predictors of intrapartum fetal stress: the role of electronic fetal monitoring. J. Reproductive Med. For Obstet. and Gynecol. 1979; 23(4): 207-212

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  63. Comm. Study Med. Prof’l Liab. & Delivery Obstetrical Care, Inst. Med., Div. Health Promotions & Disease Prevention, 1 Med. Prof. Liability & Delivery Ob. Care 73-91 (1989).

  64. Lent M. The medical and legal risk of the electronic fetal monitor. Stan L Rev. 1999;51(4):807–37.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  65. Gilfix MG. Electronic fetal monitoring: physician liability and informed consent. Am J Law and Med. 1984;10:1–48.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Rhoden NK. Informed consent in obstetrics: some special problems. Western New Eng L Rev. 1987;99(1):67–88.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Abrams JR. The illusion of autonomy in women’s medical decision-making. Fla State Univ L Rev. 2015;42(1):1–45.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Wolfberg A. The future of fetal monitoring. Rev Obstet Gynecol. 2012;5(3/4):e132–6. https://doi.org/10.3909/riog0197. acknowledging that EFM is “plagued by false positive results and other technical limitations,” but will continue to be used with “novel metrics” in the coming years

    Google Scholar 

  69. Berlatsky N. The most common childbirth practice in America is unnecessary and dangerous. New Republic Aug. 2015. Available at http://www.newrepublic.com/article/122532/most-common-childbirth-practice-us-unnecessary-dangerous. Accessed 12 Sept 2017.

  70. International Federation of Gynaecology and Obstetrics and Family Health International, Guidelines for the use of fetal monitoring. Int J Gynaecol Obstet. 1987; 25:159-167. Available at http://www.ctgutbildning.se/course/referencer//referenser/FIGO%20CTG%20Guidelines.pdf. Accessed 12 Sept 2017.

  71. Wood SH. Should women be given a choice about fetal assessment in labor? MCN Am J Matern Child Nurs. 2003;28(5):292–8.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  72. Heelan L. Fetal monitoring: creating a culture of safety with informed consent. J Perinat Educ. 2013;22(3):156–65.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  73. Grady C. Enduring and emerging challenges of informed consent. New Eng J Med. 2015;372(9):855–62.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  74. Schenker Y, Meisel A. Informed consent in clinical care. JAMA. 2011;305(11):1130–1.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  75. Anderson RE. Billions for defense: the pervasive nature of defensive medicine. Arch Inter Med. 1999;159:2399–402.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  76. DeVille K. Act first and look up the law afterward? Medical malpractice and the ethics of defensive medicine. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics. 1998;19(6):569–89.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  77. Kachalia A, Mello MM. Defensive medicine—legally necessary but ethically wrong? JAMA Intern Med. 2014;173(12):1056–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  78. Studdert DM, Mello MM, Sage WM, et al. Defensive medicine among high risk specialist physicians in a volatile malpractice environment. JAMA. 2005;293(2):2609–17.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  79. Sartwelle TP, Johnston JC, Arda B. Myths, fables and fairy tales: a half century of electronic fetal monitoring. Surg J. 2015; https://doi.org/10.1055/s-0035-1567880

  80. Sartwelle TP, Johnston JC. Cerebral palsy and electronic fetal monitoring: rearranging the Titanic’s deck chairs. J Child and Dev Disord. 2016;2(2:5):1–10.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Not applicable.

Funding

The authors received no financial support for the research, authorship or publication of this article.

Availability of data and materials

The data and materials supporting this article are publicly available and included in the endnotes.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

All authors contributed to the research, drafting, reviewing and editing of this paper. All authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James C. Johnston.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Not applicable.

Consent for publication

All authors have approved the manuscript for submission.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sartwelle, T.P., Johnston, J.C. & Arda, B. A half century of electronic fetal monitoring and bioethics: silence speaks louder than words. matern health, neonatol and perinatol 3, 21 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1186/s40748-017-0060-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s40748-017-0060-2

Keywords